Encyc

Encyc houses over 100 concepts relevant to the history of eugenics and its continued implications in contemporary life. These entries represent in-depth explorations of key concepts for understanding eugenics.

Aboriginal and Indigenous Peoples
Michael Billinger
Alcoholism and drug use
Paula Larsson
Archives and institutions
Mary Horodyski
Assimilation
Karen Stote
Bioethical appeals to eugenics
Tiffany Campbell
Bioethics
Gregor Wolbring
Birth control
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Childhood innocence
Joanne Faulkner
Colonialism
Karen Stote
Conservationism
Michael Kohlman
Criminality
Amy Samson
Degeneracy
Michael Billinger
Dehumanization: psychological aspects
David Livingstone Smith
Deinstitutionalization
Erika Dyck
Developmental disability
Dick Sobsey
Disability rights
Joshua St. Pierre
Disability, models of
Gregor Wolbring
Down Syndrome
Michael Berube
Education
Erna Kurbegovic
Education as redress
Jonathan Chernoguz
Educational testing
Michelle Hawks
Environmentalism
Douglas Wahlsten
Epilepsy
Frank W. Stahnisch
Ethnicity and race
Michael Billinger
Eugenic family studies
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenic traits
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics as wrongful
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics: positive vs negative
Robert A. Wilson
Family planning
Caroline Lyster
Farming and animal breeding
Sheila Rae Gibbons
Feeble-mindedness
Wendy Kline
Feminism
Esther Rosario
Fitter family contests
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Gender
Caroline Lyster
Genealogy
Leslie Baker
Genetic counseling
Gregor Wolbring
Genetics
James Tabery
Genocide
Karen Stote
Guidance clinics
Amy Samson
Hereditary disease
Sarah Malanowski
Heredity
Michael Billinger
Human enhancement
Gregor Wolbring
Human experimentation
Frank W. Stahnisch
Human nature
Chris Haufe
Huntington's disease
Alice Wexler
Immigration
Jacalyn Ambler
Indian--race-based definition
Karen Stote
Informed consent
Erika Dyck
Institutionalization
Erika Dyck
Intellectual disability
Licia Carlson
Intelligence and IQ testing
Aida Roige
KEY CONCEPTS
Robert A. Wilson
Kant on eugenics and human nature
Alan McLuckie
Marriage
Alexandra Minna Stern
Masturbation
Paula Larsson
Medicalization
Gregor Wolbring
Mental deficiency: idiot, imbecile, and moron
Wendy Kline
Miscegenation
Michael Billinger
Motherhood
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Natural and artificial selection
Douglas Wahlsten
Natural kinds
Matthew H. Slater
Nature vs nurture
James Tabery
Nazi euthanasia
Paul Weindling
Nazi sterilization
Paul Weindling
Newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Nordicism
Michael Kohlman
Normalcy and subnormalcy
Gregor Wolbring
Parenting and newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Parenting of children with disabilities
Dick Sobsey
Parenting with intellectual disabilities
David McConnell
Pauperism
Caroline Lyster
Person
Gregor Wolbring
Physician assisted suicide
Caroline Lyster
Political science and race
Dexter Fergie
Popular culture
Colette Leung
Population control
Alexandra Stern
Prenatal testing
Douglas Wahlsten
Project Prevention
Samantha Balzer
Propaganda
Colette Leung
Psychiatric classification
Steeves Demazeux
Psychiatry and mental health
Frank W. Stahnisch
Psychology
Robert A. Wilson
Public health
Lindsey Grubbs
Race and racialism
Michael Billinger
Race betterment
Erna Kurbegovic
Race suicide
Adam Hochman
Racial hygiene
Frank W. Stahnisch
Racial hygiene and Nazism
Frank Stahnisch
Racial segregation
Paula Larsson
Racism
Michael Billinger
Reproductive rights
Erika Dyck
Reproductive technologies
Caroline Lyster
Residential schools
Faun Rice
Roles of science in eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Schools for the Deaf and Deaf Identity
Bartlomiej Lenart
Science and values
Matthew J. Barker
Selecting for disability
Clarissa Becerra
Sexual segregation
Leslie Baker
Sexuality
Alexandra Minna Stern
Social Darwinism
Erna Kurbegovic
Sociobiology
Robert A. Wilson
Sorts of people
Robert A. Wilson
Special education
Jason Ellis
Speech-language pathology
Joshua St. Pierre
Standpoint theory
Joshua St. Pierre
Sterilization
Wendy Kline
Sterilization compensation
Paul Weindling
Stolen generations
Joanne Faulkner
Subhumanization
Licia Carlson
Today and Tomorrow: To-day and To-morrow book series
Michael Kohlman
Training schools for the feeble-minded
Katrina Jirik
Trans
Aleta Gruenewald
Transhumanism and radical enhancement
Mark Walker
Tuberculosis
Maureen Lux
Twin Studies
Douglas Wahlsten & Frank W. Stahnisch
Ugly Laws
Susan M. Schweik and Robert A. Wilson
Unfit, the
Cameron A.J. Ellis
Violence and disability
Dick Sobsey
War
Frank W. Stahnisch
Women's suffrage
Sheila Rae Gibbons

Parenting and newgenics

Newgenics is built on a foundation of autonomy and reproductive rights, but some philosophers have argued in favour of a stronger claim: when presented with a situation in which they could choose between two possible children--one healthy and one disabled--potential parents have a moral responsibility to choose the former because the healthy child would have the better life. This idea, the Principle of Procreative Beneficence, was first articulated by Julian Savulescu, and is uncomfortably plausible to even critics of newgenics: it appeals to a very basic duty of parenting, providing one’s children with a good life, and that makes it very difficult to argue against.

Principle of Procreative Beneficence
Julian Savulescu agrees that potential parents have the right to choose between possible children, and goes one step further. According to Savulescu, when potential parents are offered a choice between two different possible children they should “select the child, of the possible children they could have, who is expected to have the best life, or at least as good a life as the others, based on the relevant, available, information” (415). Exactly what this means is best explained through example, so consider a couple who is using in-vitro fertilization to have a child, and elects to use PGD to determine whether their children will have any genetic abnormalities. Two embryos are produced, and a battery of tests is performed: embryo A shows no abnormalities, while embryo B shows a genetic predisposition to developing asthma (Savulescu, 415). According to the Principle of Procreative Beneficence (PPB) the potential parents should implant embryo A because that child would be expected to have a better life, giving the potential parents a good reason to choose it over asthmatic embryo B.

There are several subtle points underlying the PPB. First, it raises questions about what it means to have a “good life”: how large a role does one’s health play? If we take the PPB seriously, health is an integral component. Returning to the example of embryo A versus embryo B, asthma would have a negative impact on quality of life because it would require management with medications and inhalers, causing inconvenience, and limiting the opportunities available to the child that would have been born. Advocates of the PPB argue that life with a disability is “clearly worse” (Bennett, 32) than life without; otherwise, they argue, it does not make sense to attempt to develop cures and treatments for these conditions, and it would also be inconsistent for us to consider it wrong if a parent were to disable a child on purpose. They supplement this argument with appeals to popularity, as many would agree that a non-disabled life is better than a disabled one, and to the personal experiences of those who become disabled due to accident or illness, who report that their lives were made worse by their disability.

Some responses to Procreative Beneficence
The assumptions underlying the PPB are not unproblematic, and have been subject to criticism by many writers. Some have pointed out that disabling a child on purpose is not the same as giving birth to a child with a disability, because while the consequences in either case are the same the actions taken to bring about those consequences are very different (Bennett, 33). Others have pointed out that an argument appealing to what most people believe about life with a disability is flawed, since those people are evaluating a life that they have never lived.

Disability advocates have also questioned the importance given to physical health in measuring whether a life is good, and have complicated the personal testimony of those disabled by illness or injury: they demand that the reasons given for the self-reported lower quality of life be made clear. To start, they point to the social model of disability, which cautions that there are two sides to the disability coin: there are, on one hand, real physical impairments associated with being disabled, but these must carefully be distinguished from the social structures that create challenges in the day to day lives of the impaired (Amundson, 109-111). Therefore, when it comes to the unhappiness of those disabled by illness or injury, they should specify whether this unhappiness is due to their actual physical impairment, or whether it is due to social structures that now create challenges in their daily lives. Disability advocates might also ask whether those disabled by illness or injury are confusing their emotions: they may report a lower quality of life due to the grief that they are currently experiencing, as they have lost their previous life, and have perhaps lost the ability to do something that they used to enjoy.

In response to the personal testimony of those disabled by illness or injury, disability advocates have appealed to their own stories in an effort to demonstrate that their lives are good and worth living, and that the self-reported decrease in quality of life reported by individuals who become disabled is not entirely due to their impairments, and is due in large part to living in an ableist society that does not fully embrace different ways of being in the world (Amundson and Taira, 53-57; Bauer, 247-251).

Parenting and virtue
Finally, critics can also question the model of parenthood that the PPB relies on. The PPB assumes a model of parenthood based on duties towards one’s children: duties to provide for, educate, and protect, for example. On a duty based model, when a person becomes a parent they consent to a contract outlining their role and the responsibilities that they have toward their child, and they have these responsibilities because the child has--or will grow into an adult that has--rights equal to those of the parent. These duties can be enumerated either as those to which all rational agents would agree (Kant, Rawls), or those which cannot reasonably be rejected (Scanlon). Such a duty-based model supports newgenics and the PPB by positing that parents have a duty to provide their children with a good life (or, alternatively, to protect them from the harm associated with disability), and giving them a way to ensure that this happens.

Rosalind McDougall has suggested an alternative model of parenting that would condemn newgenic practices and deny support to the PPB. A virtue-based model, briefly, shifts the focus from the actions of potential parents to their character, and the relevant character traits are those which help to promote human flourishing. And, since parents are tasked with raising children, the character traits in question will be those that help to promote the flourishing of children (McDougall, 184). McDougall suggests that when we ask the question “how is one to parent well?” at least three virtues fall out: acceptingness, committedness, and future-agent focus (185). All three of these are relevant to the issue of newgenics.

First, the parental virtue of acceptingness holds that, “if nothing else, parents who want their children to be happy should aim to love their children for who they are, not who they would like them to be” (McDougall, 185). The characteristics that children have are unpredictable: even if a parent could control some of them through newgenics, there are many others that would still be unknown, and that parents would only come to learn as their children grew up. Parents should be ready and willing to accept this unpredictability.

Second, the virtue of committedness calls on parents to be committed to both their children and their role as parents. Children come into the world dependent on others for their very survival, and they should be “born to parents who have reasonable expectations and intentions of being active and present to bring up the child” (McDougall, 186). We should also want them to be born to parents who are not going to run away at the first sign of difficulty. Parenting is hard work, regardless of whether the child being raised has a disability: it is a modern myth that “normal” children are easy to raise, and parents should be prepared for any eventuality.

Finally, the virtue of future-agent focus involves promoting the development of one’s children into good moral agents which, on a virtue-based account, would amount to teaching them about the virtues, good character, and good judgement. This opens the door to a world that would be more accepting of individuals with different ways of being in the world.

-Caroline Lyster

  • Amundson, R. (1992). Disability, Handicap, and the Environment. Journal of Social Philosophy , 23(1), 105-119.

  • Amundson, R. & Taira, G. (2005). Our Lives and Ideologies: The Effect of Life Experience on the Perceived Morality of the Policy of Physician-Assisted Suicide. Journal of Disability Policy Studies 16(1), 53-57.

  • Ashford, E. & Mulgan, T. (2012). Contractualism. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy .

  • Bennett, R. (2014). Parenthood and Procreation. Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy .

  • McDougall, R. (2007). Parental Virtue: A new way of thinking about the morality of reproductive actions. Bioethics 21(4), 181-190.

  • Savulescu, J. (2001). Procreative Beneficence: Why we should select the best children. Bioethics 15(5-6), 413-426.