Encyc

Encyc houses over 100 concepts relevant to the history of eugenics and its continued implications in contemporary life. These entries represent in-depth explorations of key concepts for understanding eugenics.

Aboriginal and Indigenous Peoples
Michael Billinger
Alcoholism and drug use
Paula Larsson
Archives and institutions
Mary Horodyski
Assimilation
Karen Stote
Bioethical appeals to eugenics
Tiffany Campbell
Bioethics
Gregor Wolbring
Birth control
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Childhood innocence
Joanne Faulkner
Colonialism
Karen Stote
Conservationism
Michael Kohlman
Criminality
Amy Samson
Degeneracy
Michael Billinger
Dehumanization: psychological aspects
David Livingstone Smith
Deinstitutionalization
Erika Dyck
Developmental disability
Dick Sobsey
Disability rights
Joshua St. Pierre
Disability, models of
Gregor Wolbring
Down Syndrome
Michael Berube
Education
Erna Kurbegovic
Education as redress
Jonathan Chernoguz
Educational testing
Michelle Hawks
Environmentalism
Douglas Wahlsten
Epilepsy
Frank W. Stahnisch
Ethnicity and race
Michael Billinger
Eugenic family studies
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenic traits
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics as wrongful
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics: positive vs negative
Robert A. Wilson
Family planning
Caroline Lyster
Farming and animal breeding
Sheila Rae Gibbons
Feeble-mindedness
Wendy Kline
Feminism
Esther Rosario
Fitter family contests
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Gender
Caroline Lyster
Genealogy
Leslie Baker
Genetic counseling
Gregor Wolbring
Genetics
James Tabery
Genocide
Karen Stote
Guidance clinics
Amy Samson
Hereditary disease
Sarah Malanowski
Heredity
Michael Billinger
Human enhancement
Gregor Wolbring
Human experimentation
Frank W. Stahnisch
Human nature
Chris Haufe
Huntington's disease
Alice Wexler
Immigration
Jacalyn Ambler
Indian--race-based definition
Karen Stote
Informed consent
Erika Dyck
Institutionalization
Erika Dyck
Intellectual disability
Licia Carlson
Intelligence and IQ testing
Aida Roige
KEY CONCEPTS
Robert A. Wilson
Kant on eugenics and human nature
Alan McLuckie
Marriage
Alexandra Minna Stern
Masturbation
Paula Larsson
Medicalization
Gregor Wolbring
Mental deficiency: idiot, imbecile, and moron
Wendy Kline
Miscegenation
Michael Billinger
Motherhood
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Natural and artificial selection
Douglas Wahlsten
Natural kinds
Matthew H. Slater
Nature vs nurture
James Tabery
Nazi euthanasia
Paul Weindling
Nazi sterilization
Paul Weindling
Newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Nordicism
Michael Kohlman
Normalcy and subnormalcy
Gregor Wolbring
Parenting and newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Parenting of children with disabilities
Dick Sobsey
Parenting with intellectual disabilities
David McConnell
Pauperism
Caroline Lyster
Person
Gregor Wolbring
Physician assisted suicide
Caroline Lyster
Political science and race
Dexter Fergie
Popular culture
Colette Leung
Population control
Alexandra Stern
Prenatal testing
Douglas Wahlsten
Project Prevention
Samantha Balzer
Propaganda
Colette Leung
Psychiatric classification
Steeves Demazeux
Psychiatry and mental health
Frank W. Stahnisch
Psychology
Robert A. Wilson
Public health
Lindsey Grubbs
Race and racialism
Michael Billinger
Race betterment
Erna Kurbegovic
Race suicide
Adam Hochman
Racial hygiene
Frank W. Stahnisch
Racial hygiene and Nazism
Frank Stahnisch
Racial segregation
Paula Larsson
Racism
Michael Billinger
Reproductive rights
Erika Dyck
Reproductive technologies
Caroline Lyster
Residential schools
Faun Rice
Roles of science in eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Schools for the Deaf and Deaf Identity
Bartlomiej Lenart
Science and values
Matthew J. Barker
Selecting for disability
Clarissa Becerra
Sexual segregation
Leslie Baker
Sexuality
Alexandra Minna Stern
Social Darwinism
Erna Kurbegovic
Sociobiology
Robert A. Wilson
Sorts of people
Robert A. Wilson
Special education
Jason Ellis
Speech-language pathology
Joshua St. Pierre
Standpoint theory
Joshua St. Pierre
Sterilization
Wendy Kline
Sterilization compensation
Paul Weindling
Stolen generations
Joanne Faulkner
Subhumanization
Licia Carlson
Today and Tomorrow: To-day and To-morrow book series
Michael Kohlman
Training schools for the feeble-minded
Katrina Jirik
Trans
Aleta Gruenewald
Transhumanism and radical enhancement
Mark Walker
Tuberculosis
Maureen Lux
Twin Studies
Douglas Wahlsten & Frank W. Stahnisch
Ugly Laws
Susan M. Schweik and Robert A. Wilson
Unfit, the
Cameron A.J. Ellis
Violence and disability
Dick Sobsey
War
Frank W. Stahnisch
Women's suffrage
Sheila Rae Gibbons

Natural kinds

The Idea of a Natural Kind
The concept of a natural kind has a long and contentious pedigree, but the basic idea can be illustrated by thinking about some contrasts. The first contrast is between individual things and kinds of things. Here’s a panda; there’s another panda. What do they have in common? They’re both of the same kind. We thus organize a lot of our thought and talk by dividing things up into different conceptual categories like this. The sciences in particular are rife with these efforts to classify and understand nature. This leads to the second contrast. Consider the classic films “Psycho” and “The Silence of the Lambs”; like our pandas, these individuals can be placed in a few common categories: they are both “thrillers”, they are both R-Rated movies, and so on. But there appears to be an important difference between the kinds thrillers and pandas. Only the latter is a natural kind — a category with some objective existence — the former appears to be a byproduct of our more or less arbitrary way of dividing up the word.

While these may seem like clear cases, contrast between natural or “real” kinds and artificial kinds can be difficult to draw and characterize (indeed, it is matter of current dispute whether biological species are natural kinds). Are there natural kinds of people? Do races, for instance, represent genuine divisions in the world or are they more like categories of films: projections onto the world by us? Or perhaps there are some other natural kinds of people representing certain ensembles of traits. Such questions would appear to be of interest to eugenicists interested in manipulating the “sorts of people” ,and whether certain traits are natural or artificial.

What Kinds are “Natural”?
Philosophical discussion of natural kinds can be traced back to Plato and his bloody metaphor of carving nature at its joints. Consider the task of a butcher dividing an animal into different cuts of meat for sale. An inexperienced butcher might make the mistake of cutting through bone, dulling his knife in the process — better to carve at the natural discontinuities. Applying the analogy to the sciences, we might say that the categories of some past theories failed to find the divisions corresponding to the natural kinds in the world. Unlike well-established categories like gold or electron from the mature sciences, past theories posited categories — like phlogiston or caloric — that “cut across the bone”, dividing the world in unnatural and ultimately unproductive ways.

One might wonder at this point how we should understand ‘natural’. Should we see natural kinds as only those categories “produced by nature”? After all, this provides us with a tidy understanding of the difference between the categories of pandas and thrillers. Unfortunately, this won’t quite do; for there are artificially-produced kinds — such as the element technetium — that despite needing to be produced in a lab setting seem just as much to be natural kinds as gold or hydrogen do. For this reason, some authors — John Stuart Mill chief among them — prefer ‘real kinds’ to ‘natural kinds’. The choice does not matter much, however, so long as ‘natural’ is not taken to imply ‘free from human “contamination”’. After all, some elements are human artifacts, yet this does not seem to disqualify them from serving the sort of roles that natural kinds ordinarily serve in science.

Eugenicist Applications of the Natural Kind Concept
This latter point is especially important in the context of discussions of eugenics — for one way of reading what Galton and later eugenicists were trying to do is manipulate what kinds of people exist. For example, the purported category of criminal, while on its face an artifact of social conventions (we might define a criminal as someone disposed to break socially-enacted laws), might nevertheless be understood as stemming ultimately from their underlying genetic makeup. Ditto categories explored by eugenicists, such as epileptics, paupers, or the feeble-minded. While these categories might have conventional definitions referencing certain social institutions that just happen to exist, eugenicists might propose that the traits that make some a pauper, say, inevitably stem from that person’s heritage.

However the question remains: if not isolation from human influence, what distinguishes natural kinds from subjective, conventional kinds? What is so useful about attuning our categories to natural kinds? There are a number of potential answers to these questions. Many, however, focus on the role that natural kinds seem to play in our making inferences and providing explanations. The dispute typically involves how this epistemic utility is achieved. Mill’s account involved the claim that the members of a real kind agreed in an inexhaustible number of ways. While not all have gone in for this stringent requirement, Mill’s belief that members of a kind should be alike in many respects remains popular.

One influential idea on how this should work was a reworking of an idea of John Locke’s by the contemporary philosophers Saul Kripke and Hilary Putnam. They proposed, roughly speaking, that natural kinds are distinguished by the possession of an essence, a property (typically microstructural) that was necessary and sufficient for being of that kind and which gave rise to the many properties commonly associated with that kind. The standard example is water: what makes something water is its molecular structure; that molecular structure, in turn, explains why water (in standard conditions) is clear, potable, a good solvent, and so on. This essentialist model is especially attractive in the context of eugenics, where such microstructural essences would be thought to be a person’s heritable genetic makeup; it also implies a certain picture of our power to change certain behaviors. If, for example, criminal behavior is as inevitable from certain kinds of people as clarity is from samples of (pure) water, then it is fruitless to attempt to reform such people; better to simply change society by breeding them out.

The Individualist Alternative
Eugenic applications aside, one downside for the essentialist approach to natural kinds in biological domains stems from the apparent dearth of appropriate essences. There is currently a debate among biologists and philosophers of science about whether non-essentialist accounts of natural kinds should be developed to handle biological categories — such as species, higher taxa, races, traits — or whether we should instead drop the idea that any of these categories are natural kinds. Perhaps they should be construed instead as individuals — that is, concrete extended objects connected by links of heredity. While the idea may seem strange at first, it connects nicely with standard ways in which biologists think of species as “hunks of the tree of life”. Species would be objectively real in the sense not of being a natural kinds of things (like the elements), but by being cohesively connected by patterns of interbreeding and genetic exchange. This approach maintains the objectivity of the relevant kinds, but deemphasizes their “repeatability”.

With this basic idea in hand, we can apply it at the sub-species level — as some have proposed we consider in thinking about race — by identifying lineages of people which have been relatively reproductively isolated from one another. Galton’s focus on “bloodlines” suggests that eugenicists would have found conceptual resources to exploit in either framework. While the idea that genes or “blood” would play a conceptual role similar to that of a microstructural essence suggests a natural kinds interpretation, seeing humanity as separated into various lineages whose characteristics might be intentionally modified also admits of an individualist treatment.

While the question of how to characterize natural kinds and whether we should view species as individuals or natural kinds have continued to be sources of debate among philosophers, no serious parties to these debates construe these concepts in ways that would vindicate eugenicist doctrine without supplementation by other implausible theses. I have only been attempting to indicate how such concepts could be used as a scaffold for this kind of thoroughly discredited thinking.

-Matthew H. Slater

  • Bird, Alexander and Tobin, Emma, "Natural Kinds", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = .

  • Hacking, Ian (1991) "A Tradition of Natural Kinds", Philosophical Studies 61:109–126.

  • Khalidi, Muhammad Ali (2013) Natural Categories and Human Kinds. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Hull, David (1978) “A Matter of Individuality”, Philosophy of Science 45: 335-360.

  • Kripke, Saul (1980) Naming and Necessity. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

  • LaPorte, Joseph (2004) Natural Kinds and Conceptual Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Locke, John (1689/1975) Essay Concerning Human Understanding. P. H. Nidditch (Ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Mill, John Stuart (1884) A System of Logic. London: Longman

  • Putnam, Hilary (1975) “The Meaning of ‘Meaning’”, in his Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman (1969) “Natural Kinds”, in his Ontological Relativity and Other Essays. New York: Columbia University Press.

  • Slater, Matthew H. (2014) “Natural Kindness”, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science (doi: 10.1093/bjps/axt033).

  • Zack, Naomi. 2002. Philosophy of Science and Race. New York: Routledge.

  • Andreasen, Robin O. (1998) "A New Perspective on the Race Debate", British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 49:199–225.