Encyc

Encyc houses over 100 concepts relevant to the history of eugenics and its continued implications in contemporary life. These entries represent in-depth explorations of key concepts for understanding eugenics.

Aboriginal and Indigenous Peoples
Michael Billinger
Alcoholism and drug use
Paula Larsson
Archives and institutions
Mary Horodyski
Assimilation
Karen Stote
Bioethical appeals to eugenics
Tiffany Campbell
Bioethics
Gregor Wolbring
Birth control
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Childhood innocence
Joanne Faulkner
Colonialism
Karen Stote
Conservationism
Michael Kohlman
Criminality
Amy Samson
Degeneracy
Michael Billinger
Dehumanization: psychological aspects
David Livingstone Smith
Deinstitutionalization
Erika Dyck
Developmental disability
Dick Sobsey
Disability rights
Joshua St. Pierre
Disability, models of
Gregor Wolbring
Down Syndrome
Michael Berube
Education
Erna Kurbegovic
Education as redress
Jonathan Chernoguz
Educational testing
Michelle Hawks
Environmentalism
Douglas Wahlsten
Epilepsy
Frank W. Stahnisch
Ethnicity and race
Michael Billinger
Eugenic family studies
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenic traits
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics as wrongful
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics: positive vs negative
Robert A. Wilson
Family planning
Caroline Lyster
Farming and animal breeding
Sheila Rae Gibbons
Feeble-mindedness
Wendy Kline
Feminism
Esther Rosario
Fitter family contests
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Gender
Caroline Lyster
Genealogy
Leslie Baker
Genetic counseling
Gregor Wolbring
Genetics
James Tabery
Genocide
Karen Stote
Guidance clinics
Amy Samson
Hereditary disease
Sarah Malanowski
Heredity
Michael Billinger
Human enhancement
Gregor Wolbring
Human experimentation
Frank W. Stahnisch
Human nature
Chris Haufe
Huntington's disease
Alice Wexler
Immigration
Jacalyn Ambler
Indian--race-based definition
Karen Stote
Informed consent
Erika Dyck
Institutionalization
Erika Dyck
Intellectual disability
Licia Carlson
Intelligence and IQ testing
Aida Roige
KEY CONCEPTS
Robert A. Wilson
Kant on eugenics and human nature
Alan McLuckie
Marriage
Alexandra Minna Stern
Masturbation
Paula Larsson
Medicalization
Gregor Wolbring
Mental deficiency: idiot, imbecile, and moron
Wendy Kline
Miscegenation
Michael Billinger
Motherhood
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Natural and artificial selection
Douglas Wahlsten
Natural kinds
Matthew H. Slater
Nature vs nurture
James Tabery
Nazi euthanasia
Paul Weindling
Nazi sterilization
Paul Weindling
Newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Nordicism
Michael Kohlman
Normalcy and subnormalcy
Gregor Wolbring
Parenting and newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Parenting of children with disabilities
Dick Sobsey
Parenting with intellectual disabilities
David McConnell
Pauperism
Caroline Lyster
Person
Gregor Wolbring
Physician assisted suicide
Caroline Lyster
Political science and race
Dexter Fergie
Popular culture
Colette Leung
Population control
Alexandra Stern
Prenatal testing
Douglas Wahlsten
Project Prevention
Samantha Balzer
Propaganda
Colette Leung
Psychiatric classification
Steeves Demazeux
Psychiatry and mental health
Frank W. Stahnisch
Psychology
Robert A. Wilson
Public health
Lindsey Grubbs
Race and racialism
Michael Billinger
Race betterment
Erna Kurbegovic
Race suicide
Adam Hochman
Racial hygiene
Frank W. Stahnisch
Racial hygiene and Nazism
Frank Stahnisch
Racial segregation
Paula Larsson
Racism
Michael Billinger
Reproductive rights
Erika Dyck
Reproductive technologies
Caroline Lyster
Residential schools
Faun Rice
Roles of science in eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Schools for the Deaf and Deaf Identity
Bartlomiej Lenart
Science and values
Matthew J. Barker
Selecting for disability
Clarissa Becerra
Sexual segregation
Leslie Baker
Sexuality
Alexandra Minna Stern
Social Darwinism
Erna Kurbegovic
Sociobiology
Robert A. Wilson
Sorts of people
Robert A. Wilson
Special education
Jason Ellis
Speech-language pathology
Joshua St. Pierre
Standpoint theory
Joshua St. Pierre
Sterilization
Wendy Kline
Sterilization compensation
Paul Weindling
Stolen generations
Joanne Faulkner
Subhumanization
Licia Carlson
Today and Tomorrow: To-day and To-morrow book series
Michael Kohlman
Training schools for the feeble-minded
Katrina Jirik
Trans
Aleta Gruenewald
Transhumanism and radical enhancement
Mark Walker
Tuberculosis
Maureen Lux
Twin Studies
Douglas Wahlsten & Frank W. Stahnisch
Ugly Laws
Susan M. Schweik and Robert A. Wilson
Unfit, the
Cameron A.J. Ellis
Violence and disability
Dick Sobsey
War
Frank W. Stahnisch
Women's suffrage
Sheila Rae Gibbons

Science and values

Many people think that science should aim for objective knowledge, and that we veer dangerously from this when our subjective values seep into science. And often, when science goes awry, it is because values tainted its objectivity. It is tempting to say that such mixing of science and values helped cause much eugenic science to go terribly wrong. But seeing how this view is too simplistic informs us about both eugenics, and science and values more generally.

Some Values Should Be Involved in Science, at Some Times
It is certainly true that values mixed with eugenics. Indeed, values were built into the very idea of eugenics, when Sir Francis Galton (1883) first defined eugenics as “the science of improving stock”. This means the science of increasing the value or goodness of human populations, by favoring the reproduction of certain sorts of people over others. Does the history of value-laden eugenics show that values ought to be purged from science entirely?

No. To see why, consider physics. It’s an impressively objective and successful science. Yet it would be preposterous to tell physicists that they should not value finding answers to their questions, or that they should not consult human values when recommending how their results be applied (Anderson 2004). An energy crisis may drastically increase the value we place in newer, more sustainable energy sources, and it can be wise for this to inspire and guide some research in physics. Instead of keeping values out of physics, physicists should appeal to appropriate values at appropriate times.

A Newer View of Science and Values, and Explaining Eugenic History
For reasons like this, the simplistic view that science and values should not mix has been largely replaced with a newer view of science and values (e.g., Royall 1997; Sober 2007, 2008), one informed by feminist philosophy of science (e.g., Fehr 2008; Harding 2009; Longino 1990), history of science (e.g., Bowler and Morus 2005), and sociology of science (e.g., Moss-Racusin et al. 2012; Hird 2011).

Central to the newer view is a distinction between belief and action. With regard to belief, the newer view says we should minimize appeal to values and maximize objective appeal to evidence and logic, when settling and justifying scientific beliefs. But once such a belief is settled and it is time to act on and apply it, we should always appeal to appropriate values to guide our action.

Perhaps this newer view can help better explain why so much eugenics went terribly awry. Instead of saying eugenics went wrong simply because it appealed to values, the newer view would look for one or a combination of three mistakes in past eugenics. (i) eugenicists let values judgments have too large a role in settling and justifying their scientific beliefs. (ii) those scientific beliefs were based at least partially upon evidence or logic that turned out objectively weak, regardless of whether the beliefs were also based on value judgments. (iii) eugenicists appealed to inappropriate rather than appropriate values when they turned to act on their scientific beliefs.

To make this more concrete, consider the case of Canadian eugenic psychiatrist Dr. Charles Clarke. After years of frustration working in the asylum system, he left that system and founded the so-called “feeble-minded clinic” in Toronto in 1909. There, he used patient scores on intelligence tests to diagnose “feeble-mindedness.” He often clinically recommended that people, including many young girls, who scored under 70 on intelligence tests should be “prevented from having offspring” (Wheatley 2013). Did this abhorrent eugenic recommendation of Clarke’s stem from one or a combination of the three sorts of mistakes articulated by the newer view of science and values?

Mistake One? Did Values Illegitimately Influence How Eugenic Scientists Formed Their Scientific Beliefs?
As with many of his eugenic counterparts, it is unclear whether Clarke’s eugenic recommendation was caused by his appealing to value judgments when settling and forming his scientific beliefs. The kinds of beliefs in question include relatively straightforward beliefs about data, and more complex ones about detailed psychological hypotheses. It is doubtful that Clarke appealed to value judgments to justify the simple sorts of belief about data. Suppose a patient of his, Emma, scored 65 on an intelligence test in Clarke’s clinic. To justify his belief that Emma scored 65, he probably just checked her answers on her test, rather than appealing to what score of hers he might value.

Things become less clear when turning to the more complex scientific beliefs, like the ones about nuanced hypotheses. For instance, Clarke probably believed the following hypothesis: The type of intelligence test that Emma took is a valid indicator of hereditary intelligence. Did he appeal, implicitly or explicitly, to his values when he settled upon and justified his belief in that hypothesis? It is exceedingly difficult to carry out the historical studies that would help answer this sort of question.

Mistake Two? Did Eugenic Scientists Often Fail in Their Aims to Objectively Support Their Scientific Beliefs?
The newer view says some science goes awry when scientific beliefs lack objective support, regardless of whether values influenced the formation of such beliefs. Did this sort of problem arise for Clarke? Probably yes. The idea is that Clarke’s scientific beliefs should be based on both objectively strong empirical evidence, and that Clarke should reason about such evidence using objectively strong logic. But the evidence and logic used by Clarke and many eugenicists to support their more nuanced hypotheses were weak by today’s standards, even if strong by theirs. For instance, many eugenicist psychiatrists of the early 20th century sincerely believed that intelligence tests were valid indicators of hereditary intelligence. But those tests were variations of Alfred Binet’s “Measuring Scale for Intelligence,” which was designed to reliably predict student success in schools in France, with little (if any) evidence on the relation between this and any so-called hereditary intelligence. Perhaps some psychiatrists like Clarke would have called for less interference with human reproduction if they had appreciated the weaknesses in their evidence and logic.

Mistake Three? Did the Actions of Eugenic Scientists Often Stem from Inappropriate Rather than Appropriate Values?
It is when switching from the beliefs of eugenic scientists to their actions that their mistakes are most clear and egregious according to the new view of science and values. That view says such actions should be based not only on well-supported scientific beliefs, but also on appropriate value judgments. But eugenic scientists often appealed instead to inappropriate value judgments, and this had bad consequences. Often the inappropriate value judgments were well intentioned, but inappropriate nonetheless, and sometimes wildly so. There is evidence that compassion-based values motivated Dr. Clarke’s act to clinically recommend that patients with intelligence test scores under 70 be prevented from reproducing. While in the asylum system he is said to have “worked constantly to improve the conditions of patients,” as he developed “an authentic fondness for the mentally ill,” and morally “abhorred the stigma they traditionally bore” (Dowbiggin 2005). But in retrospect many of us are appalled at how his compassion manifested when motivating his clinical recommendation, which would have had thousands of people sterilized against their will, simply for scoring low on an intelligence test.

Beyond The Newer View of Science and Values, in The Eugenic Future
So perhaps it seems the newer view of science and values can explain how eugenics went wrong. But there are important limitations to this view.

A first limitation is that its advice to maximize objectivity when forming scientific beliefs overlooks the fact that many of the concepts those beliefs are about are unavoidably infused with value from the start. The concept of intelligence is like this. When hypothesizing about whether a test validly tracks hereditary intelligence, we imply some meaning of the concept “intelligence”. And our values often help determine that meaning – values help determine the content of many scientific concepts, even when their definitions are stated very exactly and numerically. If we bring this out into the open more explicitly than the newer view of science and values does, we can increase the chance of appealing to appropriate rather than inappropriate values when determining what concepts our hypotheses are about.

Such concerns will be increasingly important in the future, as the concept of intelligence continues to loom large. Eugenics has not so much ended as changed, e.g., into bottom-up laissez-faire eugenics that results from well-intentioned prospective parents using private companies to genetically screen embryos produced by in vitro fertilization (Kitcher 1997). Some ethicists are already recommending that when a prospective parent is choosing which embryo to implant, she typically has a significant moral reason to select against any embryos that genetic screening tells us will probably have lower intelligence than the others (e.g., Savulescu 2001). Following such advice shapes human populations in ways similar to Dr. Clarke’s advice to prevent people with low scores on intelligence tests from reproducing. We need to scrutinize the values that are shaping the concepts of intelligence (and related things) that these sorts of advice so dearly favor.

A second limitation is that our methods for settling and justifying scientific beliefs are often necessarily more infused with value than the urge for their objectivity allows. The content of evidence claims often depends on various background assumptions that rest on value judgments (Longino 1990). And it is difficult for logic alone to specify which of the many types and degrees of evidence is sufficient to objectively support belief in a particular hypothesis. Consequently, authors have argued we should appeal to appropriate values to help decide which degrees of evidence suffice in which cases (Douglas 2009). So even if evidence starts to favor the hypothesis that a test validly tracks intelligence, the moral and political gravity surrounding intelligence tests in the context of reproductive technologies gives value-based reasons to demand a higher degree of evidence than would suffice in scenarios of less gravity.

A final limitation of the newer view of science and values moves us from belief to action. Here the problem is a historical one of emphasis in the philosophy of science and values. There has been much good emphasis on detailing the nature of evidence and logic in science, but comparatively much less emphasis on how these fundamental views should be integrated with more applied contexts of action—with decision-making, policy development, and the unavoidable roles for values.

One result has been that more applied views about how to best organize and fund science, so that it more routinely involves appropriate values and meets human needs, have not yet achieved the rigour that the fundamental views about evidence and logic enjoy when isolated from their important applied implications. But researchers are slowly remedying this (e.g., Kitcher 1997, 2001), seeing that a rigorous integration of both fundamental and applied views on science and values can help guard against new forms of eugenics that threaten.

-Matthew J. Barker

  • Douglas, H. (2009), Science, Policy, and the Value-Free Ideal. Pittsburgh, PA: University of Pittsburgh Press.

  • Dowbiggin, I. (2005), “CLARKE, CHARLES KIRK,” in Dictionary of Canadian Biography, vol. 15, University of Toronto/Université Laval, 2003–, accessed November 26, 2014, http://www.biographi.ca/en/bio/clarke_charles_kirk_15E.html

  • Galton, F. (1883), Inquiries into Human Faculty and its Development Eugenics. London: MacMillan and Co.

  • Kitcher, P. (1997), The Lives to Come: The Genetic Revolution and Human Possibilities. New York: Simon & Schuster Inc.

  • Kitcher, P. (2001), Science, Truth and Democracy. New York: Oxford University Press.

  • Longino, H. (1990), Science as Social Knowledge: Values and Objectivity in Scientific Inquiry. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • Royall, R. (1997), Statistical Evidence: A Likelihood Paradigm. London: Chapman & Hall, CRC Press.

  • Wheatley, T. (2013), “Canadian Eugenicists”, in the “Huronia” section of her website called Thelma Wheatley, accessed November 24, 2014, http://www.thelmawheatley.com/canadian-eugenicists/

  • Anderson, E. (2004), “Uses of Value Judgments in Science: A General Argument, with Lessons From a Case Study of Feminist Research on Divorce”, Hypatia Vol. 19, No. 1, pp. 1-24.

  • Bowler, P. and I. Morus (2005), Making Modern Science. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

  • Fehr, C. (2008), “Feminist Philosophy of Biology”, in M. Ruse (ed.) (2008), Oxford Handbook for Philosophy of Biology. New York: Oxford, pp. 570-580.

  • Harding, S. (2009), “Postcolonial and Feminist Philosophies of Science and Technology: Convergences and Dissonances,” in Postcolonial Studies, Vol 12, No. 4, pp. 410-429

  • Hird, M. (2011), The Sociology of Science: A Critical Canadian Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

  • Moss-Racusin, C., J. Dovidio, V. Brescoll, M. Graham, and J. Handelsman (2012), “Science faculty’s subtle gender biases favor male students”, Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences Vol. 109, No. 41, pp. 16474—16479.

  • Savulescu, J. (2001), “Procreative beneficence: why we should select the best children”, Bioethics Vol. 15, No. 5-6, pp. 413-426.

  • Sober, E. (2007), “Evidence and Value-Freedom”, in H. Kinkaid, J. Dupre', and A. Wylie (eds.), Value-Free Science: Ideal or Illusion? Oxford University Press, pp. 109-119

  • Sober, E. (2008), Evidence and Evolution: The Logic Behind the Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.