Encyc

Encyc houses over 100 concepts relevant to the history of eugenics and its continued implications in contemporary life. These entries represent in-depth explorations of key concepts for understanding eugenics.

Aboriginal and Indigenous Peoples
Michael Billinger
Alcoholism and drug use
Paula Larsson
Archives and institutions
Mary Horodyski
Assimilation
Karen Stote
Bioethical appeals to eugenics
Tiffany Campbell
Bioethics
Gregor Wolbring
Birth control
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Childhood innocence
Joanne Faulkner
Colonialism
Karen Stote
Conservationism
Michael Kohlman
Criminality
Amy Samson
Degeneracy
Michael Billinger
Dehumanization: psychological aspects
David Livingstone Smith
Deinstitutionalization
Erika Dyck
Developmental disability
Dick Sobsey
Disability rights
Joshua St. Pierre
Disability, models of
Gregor Wolbring
Down Syndrome
Michael Berube
Education
Erna Kurbegovic
Education as redress
Jonathan Chernoguz
Educational testing
Michelle Hawks
Environmentalism
Douglas Wahlsten
Epilepsy
Frank W. Stahnisch
Ethnicity and race
Michael Billinger
Eugenic family studies
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenic traits
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics as wrongful
Robert A. Wilson
Eugenics: positive vs negative
Robert A. Wilson
Family planning
Caroline Lyster
Farming and animal breeding
Sheila Rae Gibbons
Feeble-mindedness
Wendy Kline
Feminism
Esther Rosario
Fitter family contests
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Gender
Caroline Lyster
Genealogy
Leslie Baker
Genetic counseling
Gregor Wolbring
Genetics
James Tabery
Genocide
Karen Stote
Guidance clinics
Amy Samson
Hereditary disease
Sarah Malanowski
Heredity
Michael Billinger
Human enhancement
Gregor Wolbring
Human experimentation
Frank W. Stahnisch
Human nature
Chris Haufe
Huntington's disease
Alice Wexler
Immigration
Jacalyn Ambler
Indian--race-based definition
Karen Stote
Informed consent
Erika Dyck
Institutionalization
Erika Dyck
Intellectual disability
Licia Carlson
Intelligence and IQ testing
Aida Roige
KEY CONCEPTS
Robert A. Wilson
Kant on eugenics and human nature
Alan McLuckie
Marriage
Alexandra Minna Stern
Masturbation
Paula Larsson
Medicalization
Gregor Wolbring
Mental deficiency: idiot, imbecile, and moron
Wendy Kline
Miscegenation
Michael Billinger
Motherhood
Molly Ladd-Taylor
Natural and artificial selection
Douglas Wahlsten
Natural kinds
Matthew H. Slater
Nature vs nurture
James Tabery
Nazi euthanasia
Paul Weindling
Nazi sterilization
Paul Weindling
Newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Nordicism
Michael Kohlman
Normalcy and subnormalcy
Gregor Wolbring
Parenting and newgenics
Caroline Lyster
Parenting of children with disabilities
Dick Sobsey
Parenting with intellectual disabilities
David McConnell
Pauperism
Caroline Lyster
Person
Gregor Wolbring
Physician assisted suicide
Caroline Lyster
Political science and race
Dexter Fergie
Popular culture
Colette Leung
Population control
Alexandra Stern
Prenatal testing
Douglas Wahlsten
Project Prevention
Samantha Balzer
Propaganda
Colette Leung
Psychiatric classification
Steeves Demazeux
Psychiatry and mental health
Frank W. Stahnisch
Psychology
Robert A. Wilson
Public health
Lindsey Grubbs
Race and racialism
Michael Billinger
Race betterment
Erna Kurbegovic
Race suicide
Adam Hochman
Racial hygiene
Frank W. Stahnisch
Racial hygiene and Nazism
Frank Stahnisch
Racial segregation
Paula Larsson
Racism
Michael Billinger
Reproductive rights
Erika Dyck
Reproductive technologies
Caroline Lyster
Residential schools
Faun Rice
Roles of science in eugenics
Robert A. Wilson
Schools for the Deaf and Deaf Identity
Bartlomiej Lenart
Science and values
Matthew J. Barker
Selecting for disability
Clarissa Becerra
Sexual segregation
Leslie Baker
Sexuality
Alexandra Minna Stern
Social Darwinism
Erna Kurbegovic
Sociobiology
Robert A. Wilson
Sorts of people
Robert A. Wilson
Special education
Jason Ellis
Speech-language pathology
Joshua St. Pierre
Standpoint theory
Joshua St. Pierre
Sterilization
Wendy Kline
Sterilization compensation
Paul Weindling
Stolen generations
Joanne Faulkner
Subhumanization
Licia Carlson
Today and Tomorrow: To-day and To-morrow book series
Michael Kohlman
Training schools for the feeble-minded
Katrina Jirik
Trans
Aleta Gruenewald
Transhumanism and radical enhancement
Mark Walker
Tuberculosis
Maureen Lux
Twin Studies
Douglas Wahlsten & Frank W. Stahnisch
Ugly Laws
Susan M. Schweik and Robert A. Wilson
Unfit, the
Cameron A.J. Ellis
Violence and disability
Dick Sobsey
War
Frank W. Stahnisch
Women's suffrage
Sheila Rae Gibbons

Race and racialism

Race is a concept based on the premise that the humans can be systematically classified into discrete biological groups based on phenotypic and/or genotypic ancestral traits. Racialism is the view that races are natural and fixed subdivisions of humans, each with its own distinct and variable cultural characteristics and capacity for developing civilizations. Race and racialism are core concepts in eugenics, since early eugenicists typically warned about miscegenation or race-mixing as promoting degeneracy and social degradation, thus promoting scientific racism (see also the Roles of Science in Eugenics; Heredity; Racism).

Ancient conceptions of race
Phenotypic differences in skin colour, hair texture and facial features most certainly intrigued our ancestors as early humans became increasingly mobile and spread throughout the world, contacting groups that had been isolated geographically for (possibly) tens or hundreds of thousands of years. The first written evidence of this differentiation appears circa 1350 B.C. as the Romans, Greeks and Egyptians began large-scale explorations, recognizing various groups as “white,” “black,” and “yellow.” This would seem like a natural distinction to draw between groups of people who appeared to be physically distinct to other groups who had never seen such people before. Certainly at this time, there was also a much underdeveloped sense of human biology. There is little evidence to suggest that any of these colours (or types) of people were discriminated against because of their phenotypic constitution during this period.

It is commonly believed that the Greeks and Romans did not practice any form of race prejudice. The conception that there are natural or biological races of mankind which differ from one another mentally as well as physically is an idea that was not developed until the latter part of the 18th century. However, the development of “civilization” and the Greek city-states in the 700s B.C. sparked a newfound territoriality. The expansion of the Persian Empire in the 500s B.C. led to the battle of Marathon in 490 B.C., following which an internal rivalry developed between the Athenians and the Spartans, erupting into the Peloponnesian War of 431-404 B.C. It is with this focus on territoriality, between nations as well as internal city-states, developing out of governmental regulation and material ownership that humans began to develop deep-rooted biases for their own cultural and ethnic groups. It is also with the integration of religion and state power that a major class division emerged, with social class being directly related to birth rites and bloodlines.

Modern conceptions of race
According to Ashley Montagu (1964:37), “The ‘racial’ interpretation is a modern ‘discovery.’ That is the important thing to grasp. The objection to any people on ‘racial’ or biological grounds is virtually a purely modem innovation. That is the basic sense in which modern group antagonism differs from that which prevailed in earlier times.”

Not until the institution of slavery in 4th century Greece would there be an attempt to transform this classism and cultural bias into a biological or corporal entity. Unlike Plato (427-347 B.C), whose work The Republic provided a detailed blueprint for harmonious rule, Aristotle (384-322 B.C) claimed in his Politics that the captives were slaves by nature. Aristotle's view was not readily accepted at this time as cultural prejudice proved sufficient to maintain the established hierarchy, and the science of the day was not sophisticated enough to incorporate human anatomy and intelligence in a manner that could sufficiently prove an innate destiny or dominance; this would remain the domain of the unrelenting religious-based classism.

Even in the 17th century, European explorers and colonizers (i.e., the English, Spanish, Portuguese, Italian, French, German, Dutch) imagined themselves as superior to the indigenous peoples they encountered. But this sense of superiority was founded not on a race hierarchy, but on the belief that Europeans had achieved a level of civilization [urbanity and sophistication] unknown in other nations. This awareness of ‘national’ differences outweighed anything approaching a modern tendency to identify a particular skin-color or physiognomy with a “race.” Indeed, it was with the rise of Enlightenment thought and empirical science in the 18th century that the idea of a physical hierarchy based on intellectual and anatomic differences would become a major focus of the scientific endeavour.

Racialism and the science of race
The concept of race was embraced in the mid to late 18th century by naturalists and other scientists and given legitimacy as the product of scientific investigation. Pre-evolutionary science was premised on the notion of divine creation according and the Great Chain of Being – that god created a natural hierarchy of higher and lower organisms. The classification of the natural world by Linnaeus in his Systema Naturae (1735) would form the foundation of modern biological taxonomy, reinforcing the notion that the biological world is ordered in inalterable ways, with humans (Homo sapiens) as the top of the hierarchy. In the 10th edition of Systema Naturae (1758), Linnaeus named four geographical ‘varieites’ of Homo sapiens: europaeus, afer, asiaticus and americanus, introducing some anecdotal behavioural distinctions in line with then current European notions about their own superiority. This represented the first biological classification of humans into distinct racial groups.

Working at the same time as Linnaeus, although greatly opposed to his systematic classification, was Georges-Louis Leclerc, the Comte de Buffon (1707-1788), whose 1749 Histoire Naturelle Générale et Particulière des Animaux [A Natural History, General and Particular] was the seminal publication of its time on the study of natural history. Buffon argued that the colours of races were merely superficial, and that these variations were caused by the influence of food, air, and the earth’s topography, while structural differences (i.e. stature, body weight, height) in the races were produced secondarily by culture, habits, customs, beliefs, and practices. In attempting to derive a historical relationship among the races by virtue of their resemblance to one another, Buffon proposed a change in the study of man that would outline the divisions of modern anthropology, dividing the discipline into four distinct but complimentary subdisciplines: a) humans in general considered as a natural history subject throughout the ages; b) the races, their description, origin and miscegenation; c) a physical and physiological comparison of man’s characteristics with the other animals, and d) humanity’s origin and place in the zoological scale.

The study of human variation would take yet another dramatic turn in 1775, when Johann Friedrich Blumenbach (1753-1840) published his De Generis Humani Varietate Nativa [On the Natural Variety of Mankind]. Blumenbach, considered by most to be the father of modern physical anthropology, was inspired by both Linnaeus’s classification and Buffon’s analysis. He undertook to study the variations of humankind through comparative anatomy, using strictly anatomical features in order to define the races. Blumenbach, like his predecessors, undertook as his main goal to examine the so-called varieties of the human species. Blumenbach’s main interest as an anatomist and anthropologist was in craniometry and variation in craniofacial morphology. The principle question he sought to answer was: “Are men, and have men of all times and of every race been one and the same, or clearly more than one species?” In this regard, he stated, “for a considerable period of time singular shapes of the head have belonged to particular nations, and particular skulls have been shaped out, in some of them certainly by artificial means, it will be our business to look at these things a little more carefully, and to consider how far they constitute different varieties of the human race.”

The variations of humans were, to Blumenbach, caused by the same forces explained by Linnaeus and Buffon – the physical climate, “whose effects seem so great that distinguished men have thought that on this alone depended the different shapes, colour, manners and institutions of men.” This was, in Blumenbach’s view, the factor that caused degeneration away from the European physical form, which was seen as the image of creation, and hence, perfection. In the third edition of De Generis Humani Varietate Nativa (1795:265) Blumenbach expanded upon Linnaeus’ four race model by explaining by adding a fifth race, explaining that,

“I have allotted the first place to the Caucasian, for the reasons given below, which make me esteem it the primeval one. This diverges in both directions into two, most remote and very different from each other; on the one side, namely the Ethiopian, and on the other, the Mongolian. The remaining occupy the intermediate positions between that primeval one and these two extreme varieties; that is, the American between the Caucasian and Mongolian; the Malay between the same Caucasian and Ethiopian.”

Although the acceptance of Charles Darwin’s theory of evolution in the late 19th century lead to the understanding that species change over time in response to environmental stimuli – and that they evolve rather than degenerate – the idea that humans can be divided into discrete racial groups remains pervasive in social and scientific discourse.

-Michael Billinger

  • Billinger, M.S., 2000, “Geography, genetics, and generalizations: the abandonment of ‘race’ in the anthropological study of human biological variation.” Master’s Thesis, Department of Sociology and Anthropology, Carleton University.

  • Billinger, M.S., 2007, “Another look at ethnicity as a biological concept: moving anthropology beyond the race concept.” Critique of Anthropology 27(5): 5-35.

  • Blumenbach, Johann Friedrich, 1978, Anthropological Treaties of Johann Friedrich Blumenbach. Boston: Longwood Press Ltd. (Note: English translations of both the first and third editions of De Generis Humani Varietate Nativa appear in Anthropological Treaties of Johann Friedrich Blumenbach).

  • Eugencis to Newgenics Project. ‘What is Newgenics?’ Available online at: http://eugenicsnewgenics.com/2014/05/14/what-is-newgenics/

  • Montagu, Ashley, 1962, ‘The Concept of Race’, American Anthropologist 65(5): 919–28.

  • Montagu, Ashley, 1964, Man’s Most Dangerous Myth (4th Edition). Cleveland: World Publishing Group.

  • Blumenbach, Johann Friedrich, 1978, Anthropological Treaties of Johann Friedrich Blumenbach. Boston: Longwood Press Ltd. (Note: English translations of both the first and third editions of De Generis Humani Varietate Nativa appear in Anthropological Treaties of Johann Friedrich Blumenbach).